Verificationism and self-refutation

  • Pablo Melogno Instituto de Información, Facultad de Información y Comunicación, Universidad de la República, Uruguay

Abstract

Empiricism has frequently been said to appeal to non-empirical principles to defend empirical knowledge, which is why it has been accused of falling into some  form of self-refutation. With the advent of logical empiricism, this objection became a questioning of the empiricist criterion of meaning, noting that since it is neither a logical nor an empirical proposition, it does not fulfill its own conditions of meaningfulness. This paper intends to show that responses to this criticism, consistent enough to resist the objection of self-refutation, have been developed whithin logical empiricism. In addition, the article claims that the assertion that the empiricist criterion of meaning is self-refuting is based on an inadequate understanding of the linguistic levels involved in its formulation, as well as on some unspecified assumptions regarding its status.

Downloads

Download data is not yet available.

References

Aerts, Diederik, Sven Aerts y Christian de Ronde (2014), Probing the Meaning of Quantum Mechanics: Physical and Logical Perspectives, Singapur, World Scientific.

Alspector-Kelly, Marc (2001), “On Quine on Carnap on ontology”, Philosophical Studies, vol. 102, núm. 1, pp. 93-122.

Ayer, Alfred (1994 [c. 1936]), Lenguaje, verdad y lógica, Barcelona, Planeta-Agostini.

Ayer, Alfred (comp.) (1993 [c. 1959]), El positivismo lógico, México, Fondo de Cultura Económica.

Benjamin, A. Cornelius (1941), “Is empiricism self-refuting?”, Journal of Philosophy, vol. 38, núm. 21, pp. 568-573.

Bergmann, Gustav (1951), “Comments on professor Hempel’s ‘The concept of cognitive significance’”, Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, vol. 80, núm. 1, pp. 78-86.

Bradley, Francis Herbert (1916 [c. 1883]), Appearance and Reality, Londres, George Allen y Unwin LTD.

Carnap, Rudolf (1993 [c. 1932]), “La superación de la metafísica mediante el análisis lógico del lenguaje”, en Alfred Ayer (comp.), El positivismo lógico, México, Fondo de Cultura Económica, pp. 66-87.

Carnap, Rudolf (1991 [c. 1950]), “Empiricism, semantics, and ontology”, en Richard Boyd, Philip Gasper y J.D. Trout (eds.), The Philosophy of Science, Cambridge, The MIT Press, pp. 85-97.

Carnap, Rudolf (1988 [c. 1956]), Meaning and Necessity. A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.

Carnap, Rudolf (1988 [c. 1928]), La construcción lógica del mundo, México, Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México.

Carnap, Rudolf (1937), The Logical Syntax of Language, Chicago, Open Court Press.

Coffa, J. Alberto (1991), The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

Frank, Philipp (2004 [c. 1957]), Philosophy of Science: The Link between Science and Philosophy, Nueva York, Dover Publications.

Friedman, Michael (1999), Reconsidering Logical Positivism, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

Hempel, Carl (1951), “The concept of cognitive significance: A reconsideration”, Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, vol. 80, núm. 1, pp. 61-77.

Hempel, Carl (1950), “Problems and changes in the empiricist criterion of meaning”, Revue Internationale de Philosophie, vol. 41, núm. 11, pp. 41-63.

Lorenzano, Pablo (2011), “La filosofía de la ciencia y el lenguaje: relaciones cambiantes, alcances y límites”, ARBOR. Ciencia, Pensamiento y Cultura, vol. 187, pp. 69-80.

Muguerza, Javier (ed.) (1974), La concepción analítica de la filosofía, Madrid, Alianza Editorial, 2 volúmenes.

Neurath, Otto (1983 [c. 1935]), “The unity of science as a task”, en Philosophical Papers 1913-1946, Dordrecht, Springer, pp. 115-120.

Peláez Cedrés, Álvaro (2008), Carnap, México, Universidad Autónoma Metropolitana.

Putnam, Hilary (2002), The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and Other Essays, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.

Putnam, Hilary (1988 [c. 1981a]), Razón, verdad e historia, Madrid, Tecnos.

Putnam, Hilary (1984), “After Ayer, after empiricism. A discussion of A. J. Ayer, Philosophy in the Twentieth Century”, Partisan Review, vol. 51, núm. 2, pp. 265-275.

Putnam, Hilary (1983 [c. 1981b]), “Philosophers and human understanding”, en Realism and Reason. Philosophical Papers, vol. 3, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, pp. 184-204.

Putnam, Hilary (1982), “Why reason can’t be naturalized”, en Realism and Reason. Philosophical Papers, vol. 3, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, pp. 229-247.

Putnam, Hilary (1981c), “Beyond historicism”, en Realism and Reason. Philosophical Papers, vol. 3, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, pp. 287-303.

Quine, Willard von Orman (1984 [c. 1951a]), “Dos dogmas del empirismo”, en Desde un punto de vista lógico, Buenos Aires, Orbis, pp. 49-81.

Quine, Willard von Orman (1969), “Existence and quantification”, en Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, Nueva York, Columbia University Press, pp. 91-113.

Quine, Willard von Orman (1951b), “On Carnap’s views on ontology”, Philosophical Studies, vol. 2, núm. 5, pp. 65-72.

Richardson, Alan W. (2004), “Tolerating semantics: Carnap’s philosophical point of view”, en Steve Awodey y Carsten Klein (eds.), Carnap Brought Home. The View from Jena, Chicago, Open Court Press, pp. 63-78.

Rosenfeld, Boris (1988), A History of Non Euclidean Geometry, Nueva York, Springer-Verlag.

Ryckman, Thomas (2005), The Reign of Relativity: Philosophy in Physics 1915-1925, Nueva York, Oxford University Press.

Russell, Bertrand (1966 [c. 1919]), “Sobre las proposiciones: qué son y cómo significan”, en Lógica y conocimiento, Madrid, Taurus, pp. 397-449.

Russell, Bertrand (1940), An Inquiry Into Meaning and Truth, Londres, George Allen y Unwin LTD.

Salmon, Wesley (2003), “Commit it then to the flames…”, en Paolo Parrini, Wesley Salmon y Merrilee Salmon (eds.), Logical Empiricism. Historical and Contemporary Perspectives, Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh University Press, pp. 375-387.

Scheffler, Israel (1967), Science and Subjectivity, Indianapolis, Bobbs-Merill.

Schlick, Moritz (1993 [c. 1933]), “Positivismo y realismo”, en Alfred Ayer (comp.), El positivismo lógico, México, Fondo de Cultura Económica, pp. 88-114.

Soames, Scott (2003), Philosophical Analysis in Twentieth Century, vol. 1: The Dawn of Analysis, Nueva Jersey, Princeton University Press.

Stadler, Friedrich (2011 [c. 2001]), El Círculo de Viena. Empirismo lógico, ciencia, cultura y política, México, Fondo de Cultura Económica.

Uebel, Thomas (2011a), “Vienna Circle”, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/vienna-circle/]

Uebel, Thomas (2011b), “Beyond the formalist criterion of cognitive significance: Philipp Frank’s later antimetaphysics”, HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, vol. 1, núm. 1, pp. 47-72.

Uebel, Thomas (2011c), “Rudolf Carnap”, en Sven Bernecker y Duncan Pritchard (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Epistemology, Londres, Routledge, pp. 774-785.

Uebel, Thomas (2009), “Carnap’s logical syntax in the context of the Vienna Circle”, en Pierre Wagner (ed.), Carnap’s Logical Syntax of Language, Londres, Macmillan/Palgrave, pp. 53-78.

Van Fraassen, Bas (2002), The Empirical Stance, New Haven/Londres, Yale University Press.

Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1997 [c. 1922]), Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, Barcelona, Altaya.

Published
07-12-2018
Section
Artículos